Creation vs. Evolution

  • Thread starter ledhed
  • 9,687 comments
  • 406,871 views
Here's an excellent little video which questions, in part, whether viruses (protein and genetic information) came before or after single-celled lifeforms.

 
Its a big deal now for the folks who are upset about the seperation of church and state , to now try to introduce creation into schools by saying that a " benevolent force ' created the universe . What do you think about creation ? Is it a valid enough premise to be taught in school ?
Very first post is fraught with misinformation. “Separation of church and state” was originally created to protect the church from the state, not the other way around. If you’re using this forum for answers, then you’re already have a bias towards being agnostic or atheist. You won’t find God’s word in secular forums. For that, you have to go to His source and study. There you will find information that actually matters, including: Every knee shall bow to Jesus. You only choose in this life from where you’ll do the kneeling.
 
“Separation of church and state” was originally created to protect the church from the state, not the other way around.

I reckon it was intended to protect both from each other.

If you’re using this forum for answers, then you’re already have a bias towards being agnostic or atheist.

Um... what?

You won’t find God’s word in secular forums.

The thread with the second-most posts in the Opinions/Current Events section of this forum has countless examples of people posting scripture.
 
Very first post is fraught with misinformation. “Separation of church and state” was originally created to protect the church from the state, not the other way around. If you’re using this forum for answers, then you’re already have a bias towards being agnostic or atheist. You won’t find God’s word in secular forums. For that, you have to go to His source and study. There you will find information that actually matters, including: Every knee shall bow to Jesus. You only choose in this life from where you’ll do the kneeling.

You quoted a post that's so old it can legally drive in the US.

And I'm not sure how many people are using this forum to get answers. I think many of us use this forum to share ideas and broaden our perspective on things.
 
“Separation of church and state” was originally created to protect the church from the state, not the other way around.
You're mistaken. The latter is a part of the former, and when combined with restrictions on the establishment of religion, it forms the basis of the constitutional right to freedom of religion, which is also freedom from religion.

In the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution, the notion of separation of church and state is directly addressed in the Establishment Clause, which I've bolded below.

First Amendment
Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.
Mind you, these are restrictions on Congress explicitly. No private entity, be they individual or group, is bound to any degree by any part of the First Amendment.

"Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion," which is to say that Congress is prohibited from passing into law (which is a big part of what Congress does, as the legislative branch of government in the United States) that which establishes an official religion or favors one religion over another, or over none at all.

It doesn't always work out this way, mind you, and many a law founded upon religiosity (which isn't to be confused with morality or ethicality, as they exist--and indeed are more likely to exist--in the absence of religion) rather than the preservation of rights has made it onto the books.

The protection of the church from the state to which you refer is addressed explicitly in the Free Exercise Clause.

First Amendment
Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.
Now, just as I am regarding establishment (specifically the restrictions thereof), I'm a major proponent of free exercise, despite not being religious myself. So long as one doesn't violate the rights of another, citing belief as justification, I think anyone and everyone should be permitted to engage in religiously prescribed activities with like-minded, consenting individuals.
 
From the BB to ionization, filamentation, stars, galaxies, life and experience, the universe has persistently and determinedly self-organized into increasing complexity. Almost as if it had a goal or purpose! The anthropic principle posits that it's all about us, but that may be quite naive. Not only is everything in the universe connected, it may in some sense be alive (Hylozooism), and also may be conscious (Pan-psychism). Humanity may be a small, random error, a pimple on the butt of the universe.
:lol:

I like it, but I prefer Carl Sagan's words: "We are a way for the Cosmos to know itself"...

Stirring up much favorable interest on Reddit forums is a new physics paper, 'suggesting that we’re living inside a massive neural network that governs everything around us. In other words, he wrote in the paper, it’s a “possibility that the entire universe on its most fundamental level is a neural network.”'
https://futurism.com/physicist-entire-universe-neural-network

This paper is still in review, but there are several other reviewed and accepted papers that associate consciousness with neural networks.

IMHO, it seems quite plausible that Sagan was right.
 
This paper is still in review, but there are several other reviewed and accepted papers that associate consciousness with neural networks.

IMHO, it seems quite plausible that Sagan was right.

Did you read the article? The application of "neural network" is very narrow. We use neural networks in machine learning today. Do you think these machines are conscious simply because they run a neural network? Neural nets are included as non-linear varieties of adaptive filters. Now sit back and ask yourself how profound it would be if the universe were discovered to be an adaptive filter. Input goes in, filter gets applied, output comes out, output affects the filter. Does that describe gravity? Kinda...

This is the author's argument. Not that the universe is alive.
 
Did you read the article? The application of "neural network" is very narrow. We use neural networks in machine learning today. Do you think these machines are conscious simply because they run a neural network? Neural nets are included as non-linear varieties of adaptive filters. Now sit back and ask yourself how profound it would be if the universe were discovered to be an adaptive filter. Input goes in, filter gets applied, output comes out, output affects the filter. Does that describe gravity? Kinda...

This is the author's argument. Not that the universe is alive.
The author deliberately avoids the philosophical implications, and is very narrowly focused. On other already accepted science papers, the association of neural networks with consciousness is direct and explicit. Reddit forums are having a good time enjoying this aspect. You're just an old Scrooge trying to say "nope ". I and others less inhibited than you muse the universe is in a sense alive (Hylozoism to philosophers), and conscious (Pan-psychism to philosophers).
 
The author deliberately avoids the philosophical implications, and is very narrowly focused. On other already accepted science papers, the association of neural networks with consciousness is direct and explicit. Reddit forums are having a good time enjoying this aspect. You're just an old Scrooge trying to say "nope ". I and others less inhibited than you muse the universe is in a sense alive (Hylozoism to philosophers), and conscious (Pan-psychism to philosophers).

Inhibited? It's just a different math model used to describe the same phenomenon. I'm not saying "nope". I'm saying "you've misunderstood".
 
I've not misunderstood at all. On other less inhibited forums, this is being widely discussed.
Consciousness is directly associated with neural networks on numerous peer reviewed science papers.

"We are a way for the Cosmos to know itself"
-Carl Sagan​
 
Last edited:
I've not misunderstood at all. On other less inhibited forums, this is being widely discussed.
Consciousness is directly associated with neural networks on numerous peer reviewed science papers.

"We are a way for the Cosmos to know itself"
-Carl Sagan​

Consciousness is associated with matter and energy too.
 
Doesn't it all relate to the idea of information? In that sense, neural nets are just a best fit model for the "outward" appearance of said information. A mathematical model indeed.

Instinctively I want to deny that consciousness has any material (matter-related; so, therefore, also energy-related) relevance at all. But information needs a vector, so...


A lot of the discussion and reticence I see is simply grounded in good old-fashioned anthropo-arrogance - that we are in some way "higher beings", when it is quite clear that we are just another expression of a complex system (of systems).

Likewise, the idea of "consciousness" is just a romantic fabrication to "explain" and justify the arrogance in the first place. That a universe can be arrogant amuses me, I admit.


No material or determinist explanation of memory yet exists, so understanding information (as it pertains to what we call consciousness) is a loooong way off.
 
In my humble opinion, Earth is the only place in the universe where intelligent life has evolved. So perhaps it has had some fortuitous help along the way? I think that might be worth discussing.


POPULAR MECHANICS ›

Intelligent Life Really Can't Exist Anywhere Else
NOVEMBER 24, 2020
  • Cosmic statisticians say the likelihood of life evolving on Earth is even less than we thought.
  • Analysis suggests individual steps in evolution were more likely to take longer than Earth's existence.
  • The scientists say this research is designed give future researchers a foundation.
In newly published research from Oxford University's Future of Humanity Institute, scientists study the likelihood of key times for evolution of life on Earth and conclude that it would be virtually impossible for that life to evolve the same way somewhere else.

Life has come a very long way in a very short time on Earth, relatively speaking—and scientists say that represents even more improbable luck for intelligent life that is rare to begin with.

For decades, scientists and even philosophers have chased many explanations for the Fermi paradox. How, in an infinitely big universe, can we be the only intelligent life we’ve ever encountered? Even on Earth itself, they wonder, how are we the only species that ever has evolved advanced intelligence?



There are countless naturally occurring, but extremely lucky ways in which Earth is special, sheltered, protected, and encouraged to have evolved life. And some key moments of emerging life seem much more likely than others, based on what really did happen.

This content is imported from {embed-name}. You may be able to find the same content in another format, or you may be able to find more information, at their web site.

“The fact that eukaryotic life took over a billion years to emerge from prokaryotic precursors suggests it is a far less probable event than the development of multicellular life, which is thought to have originated independently over 40 times,” the researchers explain. They continue:

“The early emergence of abiogenesis is one example that is frequently cited as evidence that simple life must be fairly common throughout the Universe. By using the timing of evolutionary transitions to estimate the rates of transition, we can derive information about the likelihood of a given transition even if it occurred only once in Earth's history.”
In this paper, researchers from Oxford University’s illustrious Future of Humanity Institute continue to wonder how all this can be and what it means. The researchers include mathematical ecologists, who do a kind of forensic mathematics of Earth’s history.

In this case, they’ve used a Bayesian model of factors related to evolutionary transitions, which are the key points where life on Earth has turned from ooze to eukaryotes, for example, and from fission and other asexual reproduction to sexual reproduction, which greatly accelerates the rate of mutation and development of species by mixing DNA as a matter of course.

Most of these “evolutionary transitions” are poorly understood and have not been very well studied by the scientists of likelihoods. And using their model, these scientists say that Earth’s series of Goldilocks lottery tickets are more likely to have taken far longer than they really did on Earth.

There’s an iconic scene in the 2001 movie Ocean’s Eleven where George Clooney explains the series of escalating improbabilities of his planned crime. After several hugely unlikely outcomes, he says, “Then it's a piece of cake: just three more guards with Uzis, and the most elaborate vault door conceived by man.” In a way, the unlikely hurdles to the rapid flourishing of complex life on Earth are the same way.





First, we win the lottery for surface temperature and protection from spaceborne dangers. Second, we win the lottery for the presence of building blocks of life. Third, we win the lottery for the right location for the right building blocks. That’s before anything like the most primitive single cell has even emerged.

Using some information we do know, like the age of Earth and the expected end of its habitable lifetime due to the expanding heat radius of our sun, these researchers have turned evolutionary transitions into a series of existential scratch-off tickets. Read the whole fascinating study here.
https://outline.com/ruKb29




AstrobiologyAhead of Print
Research ArticleOpen AccessOpen Access license
The Timing of Evolutionary Transitions Suggests Intelligent Life Is Rare
Published Online:19 Nov 2020https://doi.org/10.1089/ast.2019.2149

Abstract
It is unknown how abundant extraterrestrial life is, or whether such life might be complex or intelligent. On Earth, the emergence of complex intelligent life required a preceding series of evolutionary transitions such as abiogenesis, eukaryogenesis, and the evolution of sexual reproduction, multicellularity, and intelligence itself. Some of these transitions could have been extraordinarily improbable, even in conducive environments. The emergence of intelligent life late in Earth's lifetime is thought to be evidence for a handful of rare evolutionary transitions, but the timing of other evolutionary transitions in the fossil record is yet to be analyzed in a similar framework. Using a simplified Bayesian model that combines uninformative priors and the timing of evolutionary transitions, we demonstrate that expected evolutionary transition times likely exceed the lifetime of Earth, perhaps by many orders of magnitude. Our results corroborate the original argument suggested by Brandon Carter that intelligent life in the Universe is exceptionally rare, assuming that intelligent life elsewhere requires analogous evolutionary transitions. Arriving at the opposite conclusion would require exceptionally conservative priors, evidence for much earlier transitions, multiple instances of transitions, or an alternative model that can explain why evolutionary transitions took hundreds of millions of years without appealing to rare chance events. Although the model is simple, it provides an initial basis for evaluating how varying biological assumptions and fossil record data impact the probability of evolving intelligent life, and also provides a number of testable predictions, such as that some biological paradoxes will remain unresolved and that planets orbiting M dwarf stars are uninhabitable.

1. Introduction
Life on Earth has undergone a number of major evolutionary transitions (Smith and Szathmary, 1997). These include abiogenesis, as well as the emergence of increasingly complex forms of life such as eukaryotic, multicellular, and intelligent life. Some transitions seem to have occurred only once in Earth's history, suggesting a hypothesis reminiscent of Gould's remark that if the “tape of life” were to be rerun, “the chance becomes vanishingly small that anything like human intelligence” would occur (Gould, 1990). Here, we explore this hypothesis.

Given that we cannot rerun the “tape of life,” it is difficult to derive the probability of these major evolutionary transitions. An alternative would be to examine the timing and frequency of the transitions. The fact that eukaryotic life took over a billion years to emerge from prokaryotic precursors suggests it is a far less probable event than the development of multicellular life, which is thought to have originated independently over 40 times (Grosberg and Strathmann, 2007). The early emergence of abiogenesis is one example that is frequently cited as evidence that simple life must be fairly common throughout the Universe (Lineweaver and Davis, 2002). By using the timing of evolutionary transitions to estimate the rates of transition (probability per unit of time), we can derive information about the likelihood of a given transition even if it occurred only once in Earth's history.

However, an additional methodological challenge arises in estimating these rates from their timing in our evolutionary history, given that the timings are subject to a sample bias. In particular, we can only observe evolutionary transitions that occurred rapidly enough to fit within Earth's habitable lifetime. It is estimated that the increased luminosity of the Sun will make complex eukaryotic life impossible on Earth in about 0.8 to 1.3 billion years (Ga) (Caldeira and Kasting, 1992; Franck et al., 2006). If a long period of time is required for intelligence to evolve, any intelligent observers on an Earth-like planet may observe early evolutionary transitions occurring regardless of the true transition rate.

A previous analysis that accounted for these sample biases found that early abiogenesis was still consistent with life being rare, as long as one did not presuppose a particular order of magnitude for the transition rate (Spiegel and Turner, 2012). Here, we generalize this Bayesian analysis to a chain of multiple evolutionary transitions, drawing inspiration from the work of Carter (1983) and others (Hanson, 1998; Carter, 2008; Watson, 2008; McCabe and Lucas, 2010) that sought to explain why intelligent life emerged so late in Earth's history. The transitions we consider include abiogenesis, eukaryogenesis, the emergence of sexual reproduction, and the emergence of language and intelligence, although the model can be applied more broadly. These particular transitions are selected because large scientific uncertainty remains around how frequent such transitions are, and because they were prerequisites for the existence of intelligent life on Earth.

2. Context
The issue of how likely life and intelligence are to emerge on planets in the Universe has long been a mainstay of the SETI-related debates, both as terms in the Drake equation (Vakoch and Dowd, 2015) and whether the endeavor is even rational (Ćirković, 2013).

While some of the attempts at bounding or estimating life are based on astrophysical considerations of planet formation, habitable zones, and other abiotic properties (Kasting et al., 1993; Ward and Brownlee, 1999; Lineweaver et al., 2004; Spiegel et al., 2008; Lammer, et al., 2009; Johnson and Li, 2012; Rushby et al., 2013; Loeb et al., 2016), some of the most contested probabilities deal with abiogenesis, and the emergence of complex life and intelligence. Estimates of the probability of abiogenesis per planet in the literature range from truly microscopic (due to the need to search combinatorially vast spaces) (Hart, 1980), over the small (values giving on the order of one civilization per observable Universe) (Blum, 1965), to modest (Lineweaver et al., 2002), to so large that they predict life in nearly any habitable environment (De Duve, 1995; Halley, 2012). Similarly, the fraction of life-bearing planets with complex life (and intelligence) can be estimated to be very high (Sagan, 1963; Wallenhorst, 1981), moderate (1%) (Billingham et al., 1979; Bounama et al., 2007), or very low (Behroozi and Peeples, 2015). Indeed, for both one can find estimates in the literature and based on models spanning 100 orders of magnitude (Scharf and Cronin, 2016; Sandberg et al., 2018).

One of the oldest arguments against SETI is the biological contingency argument (Simpson, 1964): the evolution of anything similar to humans has a minuscule probability since biological evolution is dominated by contingency, is radically open-ended, and has no determinism or tendency toward intelligence. Even in similar environments, the chance of getting “humanoids” is minimal, and most environments will be vastly different. This is the same argument used by Mayr in his debate with Sagan: out of the approximately 50 billion species on Earth, only humans evolved intelligence, suggesting a low probability (Mayr, 1995a, 1995b, 1995c).

Sagan (1995) countered by noting that if there are enough possible pathways, even individually very unlikely paths can in sum give a high probability of an intelligent outcome. He also noted that extrapolating from our case is either valid, and we should expect Earth to be an average sample, or it is improper to extrapolate, in which case Mayr's argument fails. While the biological contingency argument can be attacked in other ways, for example, by emphasizing convergent evolution (Puccetti, 1968; Morris, 2003), and supported by noting the lack of convergent evolution toward human-like intelligence in the fossil record (Lineweaver, 2009), the key issue is how representative the Earth's biosphere history is (Rospars, 2013).

2.1. The Carter argument
Intelligent life emerged on a timescale similar to that of Earth's lifetime. It took 4 Ga for intelligent life to emerge, and in perhaps less than 1 Ga, the increasing luminosity of the Sun will likely destroy Earth's ability to support complex life, due to increased surface temperatures (Franck et al., 2006) and an eventual breakdown in the carbon cycle (Lenton and Bloh, 2001). Intelligent life therefore emerged on a timescale within an order of magnitude of our star's lifetime. This is puzzling, as the timescales associated with biological and stellar evolution are driven by fundamentally different processes and thus ought to be uncorrelated.

Carter (1983) noticed this coincidence and proposed a resolution to the puzzle based on observation selection effects. Letting τ⊙ denote the lifetime associated with our star, and τ
eq-00001.gif
be the timescale it takes for evolution to produce intelligent life, one can analyze three possibilities: τ⊙ ≫ τ
eq-00002.gif
, τ⊙ ≈ τ
eq-00003.gif
, or τ⊙ ≪ τ
eq-00004.gif
, denoting the situations in which the lifetime of the star either greatly exceeds the timescale associated with intelligent life, approximately equals it, or is greatly exceeded by it. Carter argues that a priori, the possibility that τ⊙ ≈ τ
eq-00005.gif
is exceptionally unlikely, leaving τ⊙ ≫ τ
eq-00006.gif
and τ⊙ ≪ τ
eq-00007.gif
as realistic alternatives. We can also rule out τ⊙ ≫ τ
eq-00008.gif
with high probability, given that intelligent life did not emerge exceptionally early when compared with the Sun's lifetime. This brings us to the possibility that τ⊙ ≪ τ
eq-00009.gif
. This would mean that most stars will never support intelligent life, as the star will burn out before such life emerges. However, in the rare locations in which intelligent life does emerge, it will find itself emerging within the lifetime of the star, and moreover is most likely to observe τ⊙ ≈ τ
eq-00010.gif
, consistent with our own observations. Observation selection effects therefore explain why we see these timescales tightly coupled, even if such an outcome is a priori unlikely.

In the same article, Carter proposed a simple model of evolutionary transitions to describe the process of intelligent life emerging. The model proposes that intelligent life requires n “critical steps,” each of which occurs at some rate λ. He further stipulates that λ−1 > τ⊙, so that the probability per unit time of the critical step is low enough that the time it takes for each critical step will typically exceed the lifetime of the star. A number of interesting properties follow from this model. First, the probability that the final transition occurs at time t is proportional to tn, so that the final critical step is likely to occur toward the end of habitable time remaining. Second, the amount of time remaining will be roughly equal to τ⊙/(n + 1), allowing one to estimate the number of critical steps that occurred in Earth's evolutionary history simply by knowing the amount of time left in Earth's habitable lifetime.

When Carter originally proposed the model, it was thought that the biosphere could last for another 4 Ga, which in turn suggested that there were likely only one or two critical steps in our evolutionary history. Subsequent improvements in climate models led to additional research that suggested that the time remaining is substantially shorter, on the order of 1 Ga (Caldeira and Kasting, 1992). A number of researchers have returned to Carter's critical step model and re-estimated the number of critical steps predicted by the remaining lifetime of the biosphere. Watson (2008) found that the best fit was with four critical steps, while Carter (2008) suggested between five and six. Waltham (2017) went further to demonstrate that models up to 12 critical steps still fall within a 95% confidence interval. Using the Carter model without further hard steps [e.g., just abiogenesis, as in Lineweaver et al. (2002) and Spiegel and Turner (2012)] produces significantly different estimates from including hard steps (Flambaum, 2003). The hard step model can also be combined with estimates of the window length (Lingam and Loeb, 2019), or even possible early windows for abiogenesis that later close (Lineweaver and Davis, 2003).

Here, we quantify the Carter argument in Bayesian terms. Rather than hold λ fixed and estimate n as done in past literature (i.e., estimate the number of critical steps while assuming λ−1 ≫ τ⊙), we hold n fixed and estimate λ (i.e., determine what the timing of each evolutionary transition says about its rate). This has the advantage of quantifying the data, priors, and/or assumptions that would be needed to overturn the Carter argument. Quantifying the Carter argument also helps highlight exactly how strong the argument holds. Frank and Sullivan (2016) argue that as long as the odds that intelligent life emerges on a habitable planet are >1 in 1024, we will not be alone in the observable Universe. However, we find that for reasonable priors, the Carter argument places substantial probability on the odds being <1 in 1024.

3. A Simplified Model of Evolutionary Transitions
3.1. The generalized Carter model
Let us assume that intelligent life requires a sequence of n evolutionary transitions. We assume that the transitions must occur sequentially, so that the second transition cannot occur until after the first one, the third not until after the second, and so on. Let xi be the timing of the ith transition, and let ti be the time it takes between the ith transition and the previous one, so that ti = xi − xi − 1. We set x0 = 0, representing the earliest possible time that the first transition could have occurred. We assume that once an evolutionary transition is possible (i.e., once the previous transition has occurred), it occurs at a constant average rate λi, so that each ti is exponentially distributed with an expected transition time of βi = 1/λi.

The joint probability density function for the transition times is the product of exponentials:

ast.2019.2149_figure8.jpg


We can calculate the probability that all of the transitions successfully occur before the lifetime of Earth using the cumulative distribution function of the final transition time FXn(xn|β1,…,βn). This is done by using the properties of the hypoexponential distribution (Amari and Misra, 1997), which we describe in the Appendix.

3.2. A Bayesian analysis of transition times
Our objective is to estimate evolutionary transition rates, given how long it took to complete each transition. This can be found by using a Bayesian update as follows:

ast.2019.2149_figure9.jpg


where t is the sequence of transition times t1,…,tn, β denotes our β parameters, and P(β) is a prior density over the expected transition time parameters. The term P(t|β), the probability of observing transition times t given the parameters β is equivalent to the likelihood function as follows:

ast.2019.2149_figure10.jpg


However, this likelihood function needs to be renormalized to account for the fact that we can only observe these data if all evolutionary transitions occurred before the end of Earth's lifetime. Accounting for this sample bias can be done by dividing the likelihood L(β|t) by the probability that all transitions occurred within the lifetime of Earth. If L is the lifetime of Earth, then our adjusted likelihood function is as follows:

ast.2019.2149_figure11.jpg


where
ast.2019.2149_inline1.jpg
is the probability that all transitions occur before the end of Earth's lifetime.

3.3. Limiting behavior of the likelihood
We can use limits to evaluate the likelihood of expected transition times that are arbitrarily large. Setting all rate parameters equal, so that all
eq-00011.gif
, one can show that for a model with n transitions, taking the limit as β → ∞ results in a likelihood of the following:

ast.2019.2149_figure12.jpg


A more detailed proof of this limit is provided in the Appendix. This nonzero constant highlights our first key result, which is that the likelihood does not diminish to zero even as the expected transition times go to infinity. Extremely improbable evolutionary transitions will still be observed by intelligent life if such transitions are crucial to the existence of such intelligence, and this holds true no matter how improbable the transition event.

4. The Data and Priors
The model requires data for the starting and ending points for Earth's habitability, as well as the timing of the four transitions we evaluate (the origin of life, eukaryotes, sex, and intelligence). Earth's oceans are thought to have formed between 4.4 and 4.2 billion years ago (Gya) (Peck et al., 2001; Cavosie et al., 2005), which we take to be the earliest point at which life could form on Earth. Our earliest evidence of life dates between 4.1 and 3.5 Gya (Bell et al., 2015; Awramik, 1992), while the earliest evidence of eukaryotic life has been dated between 1.6 Gya and almost 1.9 Gya (Parfrey et al., 2011; Betts et al., 2018). Sexual reproduction has been hypothesized to have emerged concurrently with eukaryotic life, with firm evidence of its existence at 1.2 Gya (Butterfield, 2000). We date the arrival of human language, symbolic reasoning, and intelligence to be approximately present day, with the arrival of Homo sapiens at 200,000 years ago and the earliest artwork around 80,000 years ago (Pääbo, 2014). We assume the habitability of Earth will end in 0.8–1.3 Ga due to the increasing luminosity of the Sun. We summarize these data in Table 1.

Table 1. Data for Evolutionary Transition Timing and Biosphere Start/End Dates

Transition Date, Gya Source Method
Abiogenesis >4.10 ± 0.01 Bell et al. (2015) Carbon isotope ratio
Abiogenesis 3.9 Betts et al. (2018) Molecular clock
Abiogenesis >3.86 ± 0.01 Mojzsis et al. (1996) Carbon isotope ratio
Abiogenesis >3.77–4.28 Dodd et al. (2017) Microfossils, isotope ratio
Abiogenesis >3.5 Awramik (1992) Microfossils, stromatolites
Cyanobacteria <10 Ma Lazcano and Miller (1994) Molecular evolution model
Eukaryotes <1.84 Betts et al. (2018) Molecular clock
Eukaryotes >1.87–1.68 Parfrey et al. (2011) Molecular clock
Sex >1.2 Butterfield (2000) Fossils of red algae
Intelligence ≈0 Pääbo (2014) Oldest artwork
Boundary Timing Source Method
Oceans form 4.40 Gya Peck et al. (2001) Oxygen isotope ratio
Oceans form 4.3–4.2 Gya Cavosie et al. (2005) Oxygen isotope ratio
Biosphere ends 0.8–1.2 Ga Franck et al. (2006) Climate model
Biosphere ends 0.9–1.5 Ga Caldeira and Kasting (1992) Climate model
Biosphere ends ≈1.0 Ga Kasting (1988) Climate model
Biosphere ends 1.8–3.3 Ga Rushby et al. (2013) Climate model
Biosphere end dates are given for eukaryotic life. Extremophiles may persist beyond the dates given.


4.1. The priors for transition rates
The prior distributions express subjective beliefs and uncertainties about evolutionary transition times, which are then updated to a posterior distribution based on the observed data. Given the large scientific uncertainties surrounding the “true” rate for each transition (abiogenesis, eukaryogenesis, sexual reproduction, evolution of intelligence), we begin by considering an uninformative prior: a log-uniform distribution for each transition rate. Following Spiegel and Turner (2012), this is equivalent to saying we have no prior information that informs us of even an order-of-magnitude estimate of each transition time (βi). In addition to being uninformative, the log-uniform prior is thought to be most appropriate given that it is also invariant to the choice of parameterization of event frequencies such as the mean waiting time for an event (β) or the mean number of events per unit time (β−1). In contrast, a uniform prior on mean waiting time per se would, for an interval bounded by 10−10 and 1010 Ga, imply ≈0.9 confidence in values near the upper bound, >108 Ga, while a uniform prior over the same interval expressed in frequency terms would imply ≈0.9 confidence in values near the lower bound on mean waiting times, <10−8 Ga.

To be well defined, each log-uniform distribution needs upper and lower bounds. Note that the selection of these bounds introduces an assumption that is no longer “noninformative.” To create an exceptionally conservative lower bound, we assume each expected evolutionary transition time cannot be faster than a rapid bacterial doubling time (roughly 10−14 Ga). Appropriately conservative upper bounds on expected transition times are more difficult to produce without controversy. Although some evolutionary transitions could be the result of incremental and deterministic processes, they could also require a precise combination of extremely rare events.

4.2. Combinatorial models for upper bounds
In general, if an evolutionary transition requires a specific combination of N binary elements, transition rates to any particular state decline as 2−N. Protein folding is one example that can serve as a more general analogy for why extremely long transition times should be considered. Folding of a 300 residue sequence can be naively modeled as a random search through a space of over 10285 conformational states (the bond between a given pair of residue is described by φ and ψtorsional angles, each typically regarded as occupying one of three low-energy conformations). Given this, it would take
eq-00012.gif
times the present age of the universe for a particular folding to occur, even assuming a sampling rate of 1 trillion conformational states per molecule per second and a volume of concentrated protein solution the size of Earth's oceans. As protein sequences have evolved to fold reliably, most proteins typically fold within seconds, driven by a so-called funnel in the free-energy landscape (Dill and Chan, 1997). However, a prebiotic world would have no evolutionary process to shape such a funnel (i.e., variation with selection), and perhaps no reliable mechanism to assemble polymeric components of the requisite kinds. If so, then expected transition times for abiogenesis could be truly immense.

The transition to eukaryotic life also involves similar “chicken and egg” difficulties, with uncertainty on how an archaeon acquired a proto-mitochondrion, since endocytosis requires complex machinery only present in eukaryotes (Lane, 2011). A second potential hurdle for eukaryogenesis was the survival of the first prokaryotic host with a bacterial symbiont. Without the protection of spliceosomes and a nucleus, the prokaryotic host would be disrupted by extensive intron transfer from the lysis of its symbionts, resulting in few functional proteins (Koonin, 2011). The chimera cell would need to evolve these complex defenses faster than the mutation ratchet effect driving the (already tiny) population to extinction, which could have also required a rare specific outcome among a vast combinatorial space.

Combinatorial models could apply to the evolution of language and intelligence as well. Human language is thought to be fundamentally different than other forms of animal communication, and fundamental to our general intelligence via the human usage of the merge operation (the ability to combine two items into an unordered set) and the resulting ability to construct hierarchal and recursive expressions (Berwick and Chomsky, 2016). If hierarchal and recursive language only results after obtaining a specific combination of neutral alleles, the probability could be extremely low that each allele would spread to fixation and combine to result in intelligence. Some argue that language acquisition was subject to selection pressure, similar to the gradual evolution of the eye (Pinker and Bloom, 1990), but others argue that language arose suddenly (Bolhuis et al., 2014), and that its origin was a consequence of biological spandrels or exaptations (Tattersall, 2008). Even more pessimistic models might incorporate fitness costs associated with large brains, both metabolically and in terms of high levels of parental care (Mayr, 1994; Lineweaver, 2009).

In the presence of this wide uncertainty, we proceed by initially setting the upper bound of each before 1010 Ga and calculating the posterior distribution. We subsequently examine what happens if we change the priors to be even more conservative and discuss whether such conservative priors are plausible.

5. Results of the Model, Data, and Priors
Our Bayesian calculation is repeated for a variety of combinations of evolutionary transitions (Fig. 1 and Table 2). The posterior probability of expected transition times is maximized around the transition time found in the fossil record (e.g., if abiogenesis took 1 Ga, then posterior probability is maximized along values of β1 = 1 Ga). Dramatically fast rates are assigned very low posterior probability (e.g., we can confidently rule out that an evolutionary transition that took 1 Ga does not have an expected transition time of 0.1 Ga). However, the calculation produces an interesting asymmetry, since dramatically slow rates are not assigned low probability in the same way. In fact, the fossil record data are consistent with expected transition times that exceed observed transition times, even by many orders of magnitude (with posterior probability leveling off at a nonzero value when all βi become sufficiently large). Expected transition times can become arbitrarily large while still being consistent with observed transition times, as suggested by the earlier results of nonzero likelihood in the limit when transition times went to infinity. This phenomenon is caused by observation selection effects, since even astronomically rare transitions will be observed if they were prerequisites for intelligent observers. Failing to account for this selection bias produces results that almost guarantee that all evolutionary transitions will occur within 100 Ga.

ast.2019.2149_figure1.jpg

FIG. 1. Posterior distribution of expected transition times in a two-step model (abiogenesis with expected time β1 and the emergence of human intelligence with expected time β2). Parameter combinations of rapid rates of transition, such as those resulting in expected transition times of 1 Ma, are inconsistent with the fossil record data and thus have a posterior probability close to zero. Conversely, expected transition times exceeding 106 Ga are compatible with the data, with posterior probability asymptoting along a nonzero constant as the transition times approach infinity. As a result, parameter combinations resulting in intelligent life before the end of the Earth constitute a very narrow slice of posterior probability (marked in yellow). For example, <3% of posterior probability is assigned to parameters that result in the final transition occurring before the end of Earth's lifetime with a >1% chance (second row in Table 2, which also provides the data used for this figure).

Table 2. Evolutionary Transition Times and Implied Posterior Probability of Reaching Final Transition

Transition times, Gya Posterior weight
eq-00013.gif

0th
1st 2nd 3rd 4th L N 10−2 10−12 10−24
4.3 4.2 — — 0 5.8 2 0.068 0.40 0.83
4.2 3.8 — — 0 5.2 2 0.026 0.25 0.68
4.2 3.8 1.8 — — 5.2 2 0.041 0.27 0.70
4.2 — 1.8 — 0 5.2 2 0.012 0.18 0.61
4.3 4.2 1.8 — 0 5.8 3 0.0064 0.11 0.43
4.2 3.8 1.8 — 0 5.2 3 0.0022 0.059 0.30
4.2 3.8 1.8 1.2 — 5.2 3 0.0056 0.080 0.34
4.2 3.8 1.8 1.2 0 5.2 4 0.0003 0.014 0.11
4.3 4.2 1.8 1.7 0 5.8 4 0.0027 0.056 0.26
2 0.42 0.66 0.94
3 0.27 0.51 0.84
4 0.18 0.39 0.71
Prior weight
eq-00014.gif

A table of evolutionary transition combinations and for each, a proportion of posterior probability assigned to parameters that achieve the final transition with probability >10−2, 10−12, and 10−24

As the number of included transitions increases, the prior and posterior probability of reaching the final transition falls.


The importance of this result is that the vast majority of the parameter range consistent with the fossil record is inconsistent with expecting the final transition to occur within the window of Earth's habitability, suggesting that intelligent life is highly improbable. For a model with two transitions, over 90% of the posterior probability is assigned to rate parameters that would result in less than a 1% chance of achieving the final transition within Earth's lifetime (Table 2). This proportion of parameter space increases to 99% in a three-step model and a four-step model (Table 2). A substantial amount of posterior probability is even assigned to combinations of transition rates that have a less than 10−12 or 10−24 chance of reaching the final transition within the time that Earth is habitable (corresponding to on the order of 10−12 stars in our galaxy or 10−24 stars in the observable universe). For example, a three-transition model has over 90% of posterior probability assigned to rates that have less than a 10−12 chance of reaching the final transition (Table 2). If complex or intelligent life beyond Earth requires analogous evolutionary transitions, then the fossil record combined with uninformative priors suggests that such life is exceptionally rare.

5.1. Priors required to change the result
Our posterior estimates favored the hypothesis that the selected evolutionary transitions were exceptionally rare. However, the strength of this result will change depending on the Bayesian prior. Increasing (or decreasing) the amount of prior probability assigned to long expected transition times (e.g., by increasing or decreasing the upper bounds on the prior) will increase (or decrease, respectively) the amount of posterior probability assigned to long transition times. This is because the fossil record data are equally consistent with long transition times or extremely long transition times, and thus, only the prior rather than the data determines to what extent such extremely long transition times should be considered. Bayesian priors are meant to capture wide scientific uncertainty and a priori assumptions, so any upper bound, including our arbitrary selection of 1010 Ga, will be subject to controversy. It is perhaps more instructive to determine how conservative the priors would need to be to reach the conclusion that the evolutionary transitions should be expected within Earth's lifetime, and then ask whether limiting the prior in such a way would be reasonable.

We can calculate how low the upper bound of each prior would need to be to produce 10% or 50% of posterior weight on parameter values that predict intelligent life within Earth's lifetime with a greater than 1% or 10% chance (Table 3). To get such a result, the bounds need to be unrealistically small (e.g., setting a maximum transition time of 40 Ga for a three-step model to get 10% weight with a greater than 10% chance of life). Given the enormous uncertainties around the processes underpinning these evolutionary transitions, it seems excessively conservative to claim we should limit our priors in such a way.

Table 3. Upper Bound Needed on the Log Uniform Before Getting a High Probability of Intelligent Life

n 10% of posterior weight such that 50% of posterior weight such that
P(life) >1%
P(life) >10% P(life) >1% P(life) >10%
2 104.8 Ga 103.1 Ga 101.8 Ga 101.2 Ga
3 102.4 Ga 101.6 Ga 101.2 Ga 100.8 Ga
4 101.8 Ga 101.2 Ga 101.0 Ga 100.6 Ga
Data used for transition dates were 4.2 Gya for start of habitability window, 3.8 Gya for abiogenesis (used in all three models), 1.8 Gya for eukaryotes (used when n = 3 and n = 4), 1.2 Gya for sexual reproduction (used when n = 4), and a total habitability window of 5.2 Ga. The other transition in all models was considered to be the evolution of intelligence close to present day.


5.2. Data required to change the result
Discovering a second independent instance of an evolutionary transition (e.g., a branch of life unrelated to our universal common ancestor) would be a dramatic development that would change our estimates of transition rates. If we assume the transition rate remains constant over time, we can include such information in a Bayesian update, multiplying the previous posterior distribution by a likelihood function that incorporates the new data. This likelihood function is L(βi) = (1 − e−1/βi)τ, the probability that one or more additional transitions occurred in time τ, where τ is the time window in which the transitions could have occurred (specifically, after the prerequisite transition but before present day).

Notably, the likelihood of extremely large βi goes to zero with evidence of additional transitions (Fig. 2, red solid line). Discovering additional independent instances of a transition therefore rules out the possibility that a particular evolutionary transition is exceptionally unlikely. Indeed, multicellular life is thought to have emerged over 40 times, demonstrating that it is not an astronomically rare evolutionary transition. Finding even earlier evidence of a successful evolutionary transition could also change our estimates. We conduct a sensitivity analysis of our posterior estimates to changes in the fossil record data for abiogenesis and eukaryogenesis (Fig. 2). The primary effect of earlier evidence is to adjust the maximum likelihood peak (Fig. 2, yellow to blue spectrum). However, excluding the possibility of extremely long expected transition times requires an exceptionally rapid transition (on the order of 10s of millions of years). For example, finding evidence of eukaryotic life 3 billion years ago would still be insufficient to rule out expected transition times exceeding 1000 Ga (Fig. 2). The reason for this is that the conclusion holds so long as the habitable lifetime of Earth is roughly within the same order of magnitude as the evolutionary transition time. If it turned out that Earth will naturally remain habitable far longer than current science predicts, this would also be sufficient to overturn the conclusion that any of the transitions are rare (Fig. 2, red dotted line).

ast.2019.2149_figure2.jpg

FIG. 2. Posterior distributions of abiogenesis (top) and eukaryogenesis (bottom) transition rates for different timings of abiogenesis and eukaryogenesis. Earlier evidence of transitions pushes some posterior mass to faster transition rates but excluding exceptionally long expected transition times requires finding a second independent instance of the transition or the discovery that Earth will remain habitable for much longer than expected. If we were to find evidence of life occurring within 5 Myr of the start of Earth's habitability, this would also be enough to conclude that abiogenesis is not extremely rare.

Given the wide uncertainty in the fossil record for when certain evolutionary transitions occurred, we can also examine what happens if we update our priors based on an interval of possible transition times rather than a specific transition time. Let aibe the lower end of the range of possible transition times for the ith transition (e.g., the fastest plausible transition time perhaps only tentatively supported by the fossil record), and bi be the upper end of the range (e.g., a conservative estimate where fossil evidence is clear). To update on these intervals, we use the following likelihood function:

ast.2019.2149_figure7.jpg


In cases where the fossil record cannot definitively rule out an exceptionally short (or even instantaneous) transition time [e.g., the origin of life or sexual reproduction, see Pearce et al. (2018)], this can cause the posterior estimates to include more weight on rapid transition rates (Fig. 3, top). When abiogenesis could take between 0 and 900 Myr, our posterior is consistent with abiogenesis being common or rare, replicating the results of Spiegel and Turner (2012). However, even when abiogenesis is common, our posterior still suggests that intelligent life is rare, supporting the Rare Earth Hypothesis (Ward and Brownlee, 1999). For a two-step model with abiogenesis taking between 0 and 900 Myr and eukaryotes taking between 800 and 2800 Myr, only 16% and 54% of posterior probability weight are assigned to parameters that would result in the transitions occurring successfully within the lifetime of Earth with >1% and 10−12 chance, respectively.

ast.2019.2149_figure3.jpg

FIG. 3. Posterior distributions updated on an interval of possible timings for the origin of life and eukaryotic life. On the top, we assume abiogenesis took between 1 and 900 Myr to occur, and on the bottom we assume that abiogenesis may have taken an amount of time ranging from instantaneously to 900 Myr. Although more posterior probability mass is assigned to rates that have a high probability of intelligent life emerging (denoted in yellow), the majority of posterior mass is still on rates that are incompatible with intelligent life occurring within the habitable lifetime of Earth (denoted in blue).

5.3. Assumptions required to change the result
Our model makes a number of simplifying assumptions, primarily that each evolutionary transition has a constant probability of happening per unit time throughout Earth's history. Although this is crude, we believe this is the best model because it requires the fewest biological assumptions. Still, it is worth discussing where the constant probability assumption is likely to fall short and to what extent our results rely on this assumption.

There are a number of reasons why the probability of an evolutionary transition could change over time. Perhaps most importantly, some evolutionary transitions may have required high oxygen concentrations as a source of energy, and oxygen concentrations have changed dramatically over Earth's history (Holland, 2006). The fact that oxygen concentrations have became high enough to support humans only in the past 800 Myr or so has led to some speculation that a planetary oxygenation time is the primary rate-limiting step to intelligent life (Catling et al., 2005). Relatedly, complex life on land requires shielding from ultraviolet radiation, and the emergence of an ozone layer has also been hypothesized to be a rate-limiting step that is correlated with stellar evolution, undermining Carter's original argument (Livio, 1999).

To test this, we adjust our model so that the transition rates change over time. The most dramatic example of this is a model in which the final evolutionary transition to intelligent life has a probability of zero until vertebrates on land emerge (0.34 Gya), and that transition has probability zero until Phanerozoic oxygen concentrations are reached (0.8 Gya). This model essentially tells us that these transitions occurred fairly rapidly once oxygen concentrations were high enough, and the results show a much larger peak around fast rates, suggesting a higher probability of intelligent life emerging in the right conditions (Fig. 4, top). However, even these faster transition times are not enough to exclude extremely slow rates. For example, using the previous log-uniform prior with a lower bound of 1010 Ga still results in over 60% of the posterior parameter weight on rates that result in intelligent life with probability less than a 1 in 1012. Overall, accounting for a changing environment in terms of oxygen concentrations does not seem to be sufficient to overturn our key results.

ast.2019.2149_figure4.jpg

FIG. 4. (Top) Posterior distribution if we assume two transitions that were made possible only after high oxygenation levels. Given the late oxygenation of Earth's atmosphere, these transition times are short, resulting in higher posterior probability on faster rates. However, arbitrarily slow rates are still not excluded. (Bottom) Posterior distribution if we adopt the self-indication assumption, and weight all parameter combinations by their probability of obtaining intelligent life. Only parameters that are consistent with intelligent life are assigned high probability, and extremely slow rates are ruled out entirely.

There are numerous other ways in which the evolutionary transition rates could change over time. For example, the total biomass or the number of lineages relevant for a particular evolutionary transition could change over time (e.g., the concentration of potential symbionts for eukaryotic life or the number of candidate animal lineages that could evolve intelligence), as could the rate of catastrophes that could act as evolutionary setbacks (e.g., asteroid impacts during the Late Heavy Bombardment or the rate of gamma ray bursts) (Ćirković et al., 2009). Although these examples make it clear that the assumption of a constant transition rate over time is oversimplified, creating a comprehensive model that incorporates all factors into the evolutionary transition rates would require many more assumptions. We can say in general that any alternative model still needs to explain why certain evolutionary transitions took such a long period of time.

To conclude that intelligent life is common, an alternative model would not only need to explain why intelligence emerged on roughly the same timescale of Earth's habitable lifetime, but also why eukaryotic life and other evolutionary transitions did so. Certainly with enough assumptions one could create a model that guarantees that each transition will occur at roughly the same time that it did on Earth, and then conclude that any Earth-like habitat lasting 5 Ga will have a high probability of hosting intelligent life. However, we ultimately think that the most parsimonious model is the one in which the long transition times are a byproduct of contingency.

In addition to assumptions about how evolutionary transitions occur, we also consider assumptions around how to use the information that we exist as observers. So far, we have assumed that we can derive no information on the probability of intelligent life from our own existence, since any intelligent observer will inevitably find themself in a location where intelligent life successfully emerged regardless of the probability. Another line of reasoning, known as the “Self-Indication Assumption” (SIA), suggests that if there are different possible worlds with differing numbers of observers, we should weigh those possibilities in proportion to the number of observers (Bostrom, 2013). For example, if we posit only two possible universes, one with 10 human-like civilizations and one with 10 billion, SIA implies that all else being equal we should be 1 billion times more likely to live in the universe with 10 billion civilizations. If SIA is correct, this could greatly undermine the premises argued here, and under our simple model it would produce high probability of fast rates that reliably lead to intelligent life (Fig. 4, bottom). However, embracing SIA leads to a number of other very counterintuitive results, such as essentially guaranteeing that the universe is exceptionally large or infinite even without accounting for cosmological evidence (Bostrom and Ćirković, 2003), or giving substantial probability to any bizarre theory that proposes a large enough population of observers to overwhelm the a priori implausibility of the theory (e.g., a theory that each planet has 10^10^100 copies of itself on “other planes” would seem hard to refute if one adopted SIA) (Olum, 2002). Adopting SIA thus will undermine our results, but also undermine any other scientific result that would suggest a lower number of observers in the Universe. The plausibility and implications of SIA remain poorly understood and outside the scope of our present work. We proceed by proposing a set of testable predictions.

6. Testable Predictions
The model offers a number of testable predictions. First, we conclude that intelligent life is exceptionally rare and that we may possibly be the only intelligent civilization within the observable universe, so long as we assume that intelligent life elsewhere requires similar evolutionary transitions. Although this may seem like a large assumption, there are good reasons to believe that many evolutionary transitions have universal properties (Levin et al., 2017). It also follows if we reason that our civilization is typical. If there were substantially easier evolutionary pathways to intelligent life that did not require such evolutionary transitions, we should expect to observe this easier evolutionary history instead. Although it is hard to show beyond doubt the absence of extraterrestrial intelligence, so far all of our astronomical data are consistent with being alone (Tipler, 1980). A handful of other testable predictions follow from the model as well.

6.1. Exceptionally rare transitions
The unlikeliness of different evolutionary transitions can also be tested more directly as we learn more about the underlying physical and biological processes of different evolutionary transitions or find evidence that a transition occurred more than once. Abiogenesis and eukaryogenesis both involve unexplained or partially unexplained paradoxes which could be resolved through further research. Examples include Eigen's paradox, describing the mystery of how systems for error correction evolved in the absence of error correction, with similar “chicken and egg” problems in the case of eukaryogenesis. Our model predicts that these paradoxes and similar ones may only be resolved by allowing for exceptionally rare chance events. If subsequent research discovers relatively easy pathways for each of these transitions (as it has done for multicellular life, for example), this would falsify our prediction (Chen and Kipping, 2018).

6.2. Habitability of red dwarf stars
There is an interesting connection between the evolutionary transitions model and arguments for the habitability of planets orbiting red dwarf stars (Rushby et al., 2013; Waltham, 2017).

A typical M dwarf star will last 1 trillion years, roughly two orders of magnitude longer than our Sun, and could also be host to habitable exoplanets (Haqq-Misra et al., 2017). However, the habitability of planets orbiting M dwarf stars remains an open question, as tidal locking, solar flares, or other harsh conditions could make these planets inimical to complex life (Zendejas et al., 2010). If we start with the assumption that environments around dwarf stars are just as habitable as our solar system, such that the transition parameters are the same, we can calculate the probability ratio of final evolutionary transitions occurring around such dwarf stars as opposed to a habitat lasting as long as Earth. These probability ratios are heavily skewed in favor of longer lasting environments, by between 4 and 10 orders of magnitude depending on the number of transitions (Fig. 5, top). Assuming we are typical for intelligent life and finding ourselves not orbiting a red dwarf star, our model brings us to a testable prediction that the transition parameters are not similar, and some other factor is reducing the habitability of dwarf star environments by a factor of over 10,000 when compared with the Earth. The strength of this predicted factor is great enough that the prediction ought to be testable when using climate models or other tools currently accessible, and coincide with eventual scientific consensus that dwarf stars are inimical for complex life.

ast.2019.2149_figure5.jpg

FIG. 5. (Top) The ratio of final transitions that occur within a 5 Ga habitability window as opposed to a habitable window of another length of time, all else being equal. Habitable environments that last longer are more likely to support the final transition by many orders of magnitude, suggesting that other factors must reduce the habitability of red dwarf stars by many orders of magnitude. (Bottom) Probability ratios of earliest time abiogenesis could have occurred compared with a 3.8 Gya baseline. All else being equal, longer habitability windows have slightly higher probabilities, increasing the credence that the solar system was habitable from an early date (including an extraterrestrial origin of life).

6.3. Extraterrestrial origin of life?
When was the earliest that life could have emerged? Given our model, we can evaluate this by taking the likelihood ratio between the hypothesis of an early conducive environment (say, with the formation of the oceans at 4.3 Gya) and the hypothesis that life was only possible relatively late in Earth's beginning (say, with the end of the Late Heavy Bombardment at 3.9 Gya). It has also been suggested that Mars was habitable 100 million years before Earth's oceans formed (Sleep and Zahnle, 1998), and that asteroids could have been habitable yet another 100 million years earlier (Abramov and Mojzsis, 2011). If the rate of material transfer between Mars and Earth is high enough to consider the two planets a single environment, we can compare the likelihood ratio between an extraterrestrial origin of life and origin of life on Earth as well. In general, the model favors hypotheses with earlier possible starting dates for the first transition (Fig. 5, bottom), with the strength increasing with the number of transitions included (Davies, 2003; McCabe and Lucas, 2010). The effect is very modest though. For example, the likelihood ratio for a 4.4 Gya starting point versus a 3.8 Gya starting point differs by only a factor of about two to seven. Perhaps more relevant is a prediction that if we were to find life on Mars, it would have emerged extremely early and have a common ancestor with life on Earth.

7. Conclusions
It took approximately 4.5 billion years for a series of evolutionary transitions resulting in intelligent life to unfold on Earth. In another billion years, the increasing luminosity of the Sun will make Earth uninhabitable for complex life. Intelligence therefore emerged late in Earth's lifetime. Together with the dispersed timing of key evolutionary transitions and plausible priors, one can conclude that the expected transition times likely exceed the lifetime of Earth, perhaps by many orders of magnitude. In turn, this suggests that intelligent life is likely to be exceptionally rare. Arriving at an alternative conclusion would require either exceptionally conservative priors, finding additional instances of evolutionary transitions, or adopting an alternative model that can explain why evolutionary transitions took so long on Earth without appealing to rare stochastic occurrences. The model provides a number of other testable predictions, including that M dwarf stars are uninhabitable, that many biological paradoxes will remain unsolved without allowing for extremely unlikely events, and that, counterintuitively, we might be slightly more likely to find simple life on Mars.

Author Disclosure Statement
No competing financial interests exist.

Funding Information
This project received funding from Jaan Tallinn, Open Philanthropy, and from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union's Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (grant agreement No. 669751). This paper reflects only the view of the authors: the ERCEA is not responsible for any use that may be made of the information it contains.

Abbreviation Used
SIA
Self Indication Assumption

SETI
Search for extraterrestrial intelligence

LHB
Late Heavy Bombardment

Ma
million years

Ga
billion years

Mya
million years ago

Gya
billion years ago

Appendix
The Generalized Carter Model
Let us assume that intelligent life requires a sequence of n evolutionary transitions. We assume that the transitions must occur sequentially, so that the second transition cannot occur until after the first one, the third not until after the second, and so on. Let xi be the timing of the ith transition, and let ti be the time it takes between the ith transition and the previous one, so that ti = xi − xi − 1. We set x0 = 0, representing the earliest possible time that the first transition could have occurred. We assume that once an evolutionary transition is possible (i.e., once the previous transition has occurred), it occurs at a constant average rate λi, so that each ti is exponentially distributed with an expected transition time of βi = 1/λi. The joint probability density function for the transition times is the product of exponentials:

ast.2019.2149_figure8.jpg


The probability that n transitions successfully occur before a certain point in time (e.g., the lifetime of Earth) can be found by computing the cumulative distribution function

ast.2019.2149_figure6.jpg

https://www.liebertpub.com/doi/10.1089/ast.2019.2149
 
Last edited:
Cosmic statisticians say the likelihood of life evolving on Earth is even less than we thought.

There are many answers to that statement.

Analysis suggests individual steps in evolution were more likely to take longer than Earth's existence.

I don't see that in that article, and we know evolution can take just a few years in some species... where is this all going?

For decades, scientists and even philosophers have chased many explanations for the Fermi paradox. How, in an infinitely big universe, can we be the only intelligent life we’ve ever encountered?

There are problems with the Fermi Paradox, one of which you hinted at with "infinitely big". I'm not sure the universe is infinitely big, but it's bloody astonishingly bigly big nonetheless. Are all these peoples alive at the same time? Are they remotely near to us in universal terms? Are they intelligent like us with the same limited means of travel?

Broadly speaking the Paradox is only one if you presume that intelligent, contemporary, inter-galaxial races exist... and that they have any interest in our particular star and its orbitals. Perhaps somebody has noticed us but there's some kind of Prime Directive that specificially forbids "them" from reaching out until we too are interstellar. At its root the Fermi Paradox is a good illustration of the supremacist arrogance that makes humans so incredibly successful at surviving.
 
The universe is far bigger than we can conceive, and we're only able to observe the tiniest fraction of it, and most of what we're observing is stuff that happened eons ago.

To quote Contact/Carl Sagan: "There are 400 billion stars just in our galaxy alone. If only one out of a million of those had planets, and if just one out of a million of those had life, and if just one out of a million of those had intelligent life, there would be literally millions of civilisations out there. But if it's just us, seems like an awful waste of space."
 
There are problems with the Fermi Paradox, one of which you hinted at with "infinitely big". I'm not sure the universe is infinitely big, but it's bloody astonishingly bigly big nonetheless. Are all these peoples alive at the same time? Are they remotely near to us in universal terms? Are they intelligent like us with the same limited means of travel?

Thing is, we have found tons of earth-like planets in our vicinity that could support some form of complex life as we know it right now, and according to scientists they have been stable long enough for complex life (unlike Mars for example). So earth-like planets, of which we know can support life, are apparently a dime a dozen. And that excludes all the planets completely covered with water and other more exotics places that could still harbor more exotic lifeforms.

Whats interesting is that there are experiments re-creating the conditions that existed when the first complex systems started to develop on earth, (amino-acids) and so far in none of those experiments anything interesting happened.

Another possibility is that intelligence itself is pretty rare because it is not necessarily the best solution of evolution. Bacteria are hardly intelligent, yet they have spread all over the planet and the survival of their species is pretty much guaranteed. It is even possible that bacteria speeds all over the galaxy via asteroids, making them an space-faring race, before humans. :scared:
So maybe there are many planets that harbor life which simply isn't very intelligent. Could it be possible that we are the most intelligent race?

My favorite theory is that this is a simulation and its bloody hard to simulate intelligent beings, so in order to keep computation down to a bearable level there is only one intelligent race simulated at a time. :lol:
 
Thing is, we have found tons of earth-like planets in our vicinity that could support some form of complex life as we know it right now, and according to scientists they have been stable long enough for complex life (unlike Mars for example). So earth-like planets, of which we know can support life, are apparently a dime a dozen. And that excludes all the planets completely covered with water and other more exotics places that could still harbor more exotic lifeforms.

Planets where life could be are different to planets where life is. Based on our sample of 1 we simply have no idea how often this might happen. Or if it has happened somewhere, or is yet to. The idea of "exotic" is a difficult one too - there's no reason to think that we'll encounter familiar bipedal hominids.

Whats interesting is that there are experiments re-creating the conditions that existed when the first complex systems started to develop on earth, (amino-acids) and so far in none of those experiments anything interesting happened.

Yes and no. We don't know those early conditions very well and those experiments take us towards discovering that as much as they take us towards understanding the creation of life. Recreation of early experiments in the field have yielded far more information than the experiments' creators were first aware of.

Another possibility is that intelligence itself is pretty rare because it is not necessarily the best solution of evolution. Bacteria are hardly intelligent, yet they have spread all over the planet and the survival of their species is pretty much guaranteed. It is even possible that bacteria speeds all over the galaxy via asteroids, making them an space-faring race, before humans. :scared:

Which is part of the search for life but not necessarily relevant to the search for intelligent life, the basis of the Paradox.

It is even possible that bacteria speeds all over the galaxy via asteroids, making them an space-faring race, before humans. :scared:

Yes, although "race" is totally the wrong word in this context. It also requires those bacteria to be "alive" on the asteroid, or at least in a carnatable state, and for them to successfully transfer to another body. Otherwise they're doing what we are - travelling billions of miles through space clinging to a rock.

Could it be possible that we are the most intelligent race?

It's possible. The general consensus seems to be that it's statistically unlikely, but it remains possible.
 
Intelligent Life Really Can't Exist Anywhere Else
NOVEMBER 24, 2020
  • Cosmic statisticians say the likelihood of life evolving on Earth is even less than we thought.
  • Analysis suggests individual steps in evolution were more likely to take longer than Earth's existence.
  • The scientists say this research is designed give future researchers a foundation.

I didn't find that paper very convincing. The key problem is that all the probabilities they worked out are based on a statistical sample of 1. It's like throwing a die until you get a six and then stopping to calculate the probability: you get a huge margin of error.
 
I didn't find that paper very convincing. The key problem is that all the probabilities they worked out are based on a statistical sample of 1. It's like throwing a die until you get a six and then stopping to calculate the probability: you get a huge margin of error.

And that's really the problem with the Drake Equation and all the probability of life stuff. You can try and put together meaningful guesses as to the numbers that should be feeding the prediction, but they're all ultimately guesses and therefore any result is also a guess.

We've observed one example of a planet bearing life. As far as examining planets to a level of detail that we're reasonably certain that they do or don't contain life, we've probably only done that once as well. We can't even say with certainty that none of the other planets in the solar system contain life.

Making broad sweeping statements about the existence of life in the universe feels like a child who has never left her room except to go to the bathroom once saying "well no one has ever come and visited me and I don't hear anything so clearly there are no other people anywhere". Girl, you haven't even gone into other rooms and looked, get off your dang high horse.
 
I'm probably the first (and only) man on the forum to say that non-peer reviewed science is about as useful as a steaming pile of bull ****. However, a scoop of it in your mind might fertilize an interesting idea.

I will be even more interested if and when the Oxford paper is reviewed and formally published.
 
I note with wry amusement that not one of the girls has considered the possibility that the science may be correct, but instinctively assume it to be incorrect. However I do applaud the rather fearful query,
...where is this all going?
 
Last edited:
I'm probably the first (and only) man on the forum to say that non-peer reviewed science is about as useful as a steaming pile of bull ****.

Yep, that's just you. You're a real ground breaker with that one. Revolutionary thought. Try and rein in the staggering insights please, the rest of us mere mortals can't keep up with your brilliance.

I note with wry amusement that not one of the girls has considered the possibility that the science may be correct, but instinctively assume it to be incorrect.

I note with wry amusement that you still don't actually get how science works. Bollocks like this is for all intents and purposes unfalsifiable. It's an entire paper full of probabilities and maybes, and I include in that their "testable" predictions. Which include either finding life around other stars, finding life on Mars, or making a breakthrough in the science of creating life. Technically at some point in the distant future we might have the technological skill to actually go and test some of this stuff, but for the foreseeable future this is little more than mathematical masturbation. It certainly doesn't warrant the hyperbolic PM title - you'd have been much better leading with the true title of the paper which is at least truthful, using as it does the terms "suggests" and "rare".

Claiming that something "may be correct" is missing the point. There's plenty of fiction books out there that contain scientific concepts that are rigorously conceived and could be correct. We don't accord them the same status as verifiable science, but neither do we outright dismiss them. It may be possible to make a space elevator, or a ringworld, or an Alcubierre drive.

But if someone is claiming that it is possible, then they're going to get shouted down unless they actually have some convincing proof. And fancy math alone rarely constitutes a convincing proof of practical concepts.

Which gets us to the stage where I point out that the authors claimed nothing of the sort.

Together with the dispersed timing of key evolutionary transitions and plausible priors, one can conclude that the expected transition times likely exceed the lifetime of Earth, perhaps by many orders of magnitude. In turn, this suggests that intelligent life is likely to be exceptionally rare.

For a scientist, that's a whole lot of qualifying your statements. The authors are very much not comfortable with making broad, definitive statements from his data like you and Popular Mechanics have. They understand that at best this is a mathematical treatment that attempts to define limits for probabilities based on known data. They understand that this relies on a bunch of assumptions that may be very wrong, and they understand the need for falsifiability to the extent that they included a section specifically to address that concern (however poorly). Normal scientific papers do not include such a section, as such tests of falsifiability should be self-evident to anyone in the field.

I still think that the paper is bollocks, but at least the authors understand the limitations of what they're trying to present. You apparently don't.

You know how you hate when other people take your words and twist them into something that you haven't said? Congratulations, you've become what you hated.
 
I like the way the article's writer Caroline Delbert compares the paper to some George Clooney movie she was perhaps watching on the box with a glass of wine and goes on to pose this impossible choice at the end of the article between which there's a lot of wiggle room.

Screenshot_20201128-064718_Chrome.jpg


I guess nuance and popular mechanics don't go hand in hand and one clickbait headline is worth a thousand words or more.
 
Last edited:
My own hunch on the issue of intelligent life elsewhere in the Universe is that yes there probably has been, and yes there probably will be but the chances are there are none right now other than ourselves.

Yes the Universe is vast with near countless galaxies, solar systems and planets. It is also long lived - VERY. The human race will likely only exist for a mere blip on Universe timescales and our period as scientific species a mere fraction of that. A thousand different intelligent species could come and go and yet never exist at the same time.

When we bring size back into the equation then we add in the unlikelihood that any of these rare species will ever exist in our time frame AND be discoverable.
 
Last edited:
Back